共查询到20条相似文献,搜索用时 9 毫秒
1.
Under stochastic dominance Choquet-expected utility and anticipated utility are identical 总被引:6,自引:0,他引:6
Peter Wakker 《Theory and Decision》1990,29(2):119-132
The aim of this paper is to convince the reader that Choquet-expected utility, as initiated by Schmeidler (1982, 1989) for decision making under uncertainty, when formulated for decision making under risk naturally leads to anticipated utility, as initiated by Quiggin/Yaari. Thus the two generalizations of expected utility in fact are one. 相似文献
2.
A theory of coarse utility 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
3.
Pavlo R. Blavatskyy 《Journal of Risk and Uncertainty》2007,34(3):259-286
This paper proposes a new decision theory of how individuals make random errors when they compute the expected utility of
risky lotteries. When distorted by errors, the expected utility of a lottery never exceeds (falls below) the utility of the
highest (lowest) outcome. This assumption implies that errors are likely to overvalue (undervalue) lotteries with expected
utility close to the utility of the lowest (highest) outcome. Proposed theory explains many stylized empirical facts such
as the fourfold pattern of risk attitudes, common consequence effect (Allais paradox), common ratio effect and violations
of betweenness. Theory fits the data from ten well-known experimental studies at least as well as cumulative prospect theory.
相似文献
Pavlo R. BlavatskyyEmail: |
4.
Cumulative prospect theory was introduced by Tversky and Kahneman so as to combine the empirical realism of their original prospect theory with the theoretical advantages of Quiggin's rank-dependent utility. Preference axiomatizations were provided in several papers. All those axiomatizations, however, only consider decision under uncertainty. No axiomatization has been provided as yet for decision under risk, i.e., the case in which given probabilities are transformed. Providing the latter is the purpose of this note. The resulting axiomatization is considerably simpler than that for uncertainty. 相似文献
5.
A Note on Luce-Fishburn Axiomatization of Rank-Dependent Utility 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
Liping Liu 《Journal of Risk and Uncertainty》2004,28(1):55-71
In this paper, I provide a new axiomatization for rank-dependent utilities. I show that, along with weak order, dominance, and the binary rank-dependent representation, the decomposition of certainty equivalents is sufficient to derive the general rank-dependent model of Luce and Fishburn (1991, 1995). My axiomatization not only simplifies and generalizes the theory proposed by Luce and Fishburn (1991, 1995) but also is more empirically appealing. The result is comparable to that obtained by Quiggin (1982) in the sense that both involve a sort of decomposition of certainty equivalents and both do not use compound lotteries. However, my axiomatization does not have the restriction that the weight of probability 1/2 is 1/2. 相似文献
6.
Testing Descriptive Utility Theories: Violations of Stochastic Dominance and Cumulative Independence 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
Choices between gambles show systematic violations of stochastic dominance. For example, most people choose ($6, .05; $91, .03; $99, .92) over ($6, .02; $8, .03; $99, .95), violating dominance. Choices also violate two cumulative independence conditions: (1) If S = (z, r; x, p; y, q) R = (z, r; x, p; y, q) then S = (x, r; y, p + q) R = (x, r + p; y, q). (2) If S = (x, p; y, q; z, r) R = (x, p; y, q; z, r) then S = (x, p + q; y, r) R = (x, p; y, q + r), where 0 < z < x < x < y < y < y < z.Violations contradict any utility theory satisfying transivity, outcome monotonicity, coalescing, and comonotonic independence. Because rank-and sign-dependent utility theories, including cumulative prospect theory (CPT), satisfy these properties, they cannot explain these results.However, the configural weight model of Birnbaum and McIntosh (1996) predicted the observed violations of stochastic dominance, cumulative independence, and branch independence. This model assumes the utility of a gamble is a weighted average of outcomes\' utilities, where each configural weight is a function of the rank order of the outcome\'s value among distinct values and that outcome\'s probability. The configural weight, TAX model with the same number of parameters as CPT fit the data of most individuals better than the model of CPT. 相似文献
7.
Recent experimental studies have focused on fitting parameterized functional forms to cumulative prospect theory's weighting function. This paper examines the behavioral implications of the functional forms and the estimated parameters. We find that none of the parameterizations can simultaneously account for gambling on unlikely gains and the Allais paradox behavior or other strong choice patterns from experiments. Parameter estimates that lead to reasonable amounts of insurance and gambling behavior tend to also generate large risk premia. Taken as a whole, the analysis suggests that the functional forms proposed in the literature are not suitable for generalization to applied settings. 相似文献
8.
9.
John Quiggin 《Theory and Decision》1995,38(2):153-171
Generalized expected utility models have enjoyed considerable success in explaining observed choices under uncertainty. However, there has been only limited progress in deriving comparative static results. This paper presents a general framework which permits the incorporation of a wide range of generalized expected utility models, but is sufficiently powerful to permit the derivation of comparative static results. The central idea is to represent preferences by the expected utility of a transformed probability distribution. 相似文献
10.
Stephen A. Clark 《Theory and Decision》1993,34(1):21-45
We study a Linear Axiom of Revealed Preference (LARP) that characterizes the consistency of a choice function with respect to a preference order satisfying the independence axiom. In addition, LARP characterizes lexicographic linear utility rationality when the choice space is a convex subset of a finite-dimensional real vector space, and LARP characterizes linear utility rationality when the choice space corresponds to a finite choice experiment. 相似文献
11.
Pavlo Blavatskyy 《Theory and Decision》2006,60(2-3):315-334
Elicitation methods in decision-making under risk allow us to infer the utilities of outcomes as well as the probability weights
from the observed preferences of an individual. An optimally efficient elicitation method is proposed, which takes the inevitable
distortion of preferences by random errors into account and minimizes the effect of such errors on the inferred utility and
probability weighting functions. Under mild assumptions, the optimally efficient method for eliciting utilities and probability
weights is the following three-stage procedure. First, a probability is elicited whose subjective weight is one half. Second,
the utility function is elicited through the midpoint chaining certainty equivalent method using the probability elicited
at the first stage. Finally, the probability weighting function is elicited through the probability equivalent method. 相似文献
12.
We develop a model of Disappointment in which disappointment and elation arise from comparing the outcome received, not with
an expected value as in previous models, but rather with the other individual outcomes of the lottery. This approach may better
reflect the way individuals are liable to experience disappointment. The model obtained accounts for classic behavioral deviations
from the normative theory, offers a richer structure than previous disappointment models, and leads to a Rank-Dependent Utility
formulation in a transparent way. Thus, our disappointment model may provide a clear psychological rationale for the subjective
transformation of probabilities. 相似文献
13.
An experimental test of several generalized utility theories 总被引:5,自引:9,他引:5
Colin F. Camerer 《Journal of Risk and Uncertainty》1989,2(1):61-104
There is much evidence that people willingly violate expected utility theory when making choices. Several axiomatic theories have been proposed to explain some of this evidence, but there are few data that discriminate between the theories. To gather such data, an experiment was conducted using pairs of gambles with three levels of outcomes and many combinations of probabilities. Most typical findings were replicated, including the common consequence effect and different risk attitudes for gains and losses. There is evidence of both fanning out and fanning in of indifference curves, and both quasiconcavity and quasiconvexity of preferences. No theory can explain all the data, but prospect theory and the hypothesis that indifference curves fan out can explain most of them.The Wharton School,University of Pennsylvania 相似文献
14.
Yutaka Nakamura 《Journal of Risk and Uncertainty》1993,6(1):33-48
This article is concerned with thresholds of discrimination of preference judgments under uncertainty. We establish an axiomatic characterization for a threshold representation, where thresholds are represented by inexact measurement of subjective probabilities, i.e., upper and lower probabilities. Since upper and lower probabilities need not be additive, the representational form adopts the Choquet integration. 相似文献
15.
Different experimental procedures for obtaining valuations of risky actions: Implications for utility theory 总被引:1,自引:0,他引:1
Graham Loomes 《Theory and Decision》1988,25(1):1-23
Three different methods of obtaining certainty equivalent valuations of four simple gambles were used with a sample of 358 people paid entirely according to their decisions. The results caution against oversimplistic utility models, and exhibit various characteristics that invite further investigation, including: a marked tendency to round valuations up or down; a tendency to value riskier actions more highly than less risky actions; and multimodal distributions of valuations which, despite their unusual shape, appeared to constitute an identifiable pattern of behaviour. 相似文献
16.
The widely observed preference for lotteries involving precise rather than vague of ambiguous probabilities is called ambiguity aversion. Ambiguity aversion cannot be predicted or explained by conventional expected utility models. For the subjectively weighted linear utility (SWLU) model, we define both probability and payoff premiums for ambiguity, and introduce alocal ambiguity aversion function a(u) that is proportional to these ambiguity premiums for small uncertainties. We show that one individual's ambiguity premiums areglobally larger than another's if and only if hisa(u) function is everywhere larger. Ambiguity aversion has been observed to increase 1) when the mean probability of gain increases and 2) when the mean probability of loss decreases. We show that such behavior is equivalent toa(u) increasing in both the gain and loss domains. Increasing ambiguity aversion also explains the observed excess of sellers' over buyers' prices for insurance against an ambiguous probability of loss. 相似文献
17.
The assumption of bounded utility function resolves the St. Petersburg paradox. The justification for such a bound is provided by Brito, who argues that limited time will bound the utility function. However, a reformulated St. Petersburg game, which is played for both money and time, effectively circumvents Brito's justification for a bound. Hence, no convincing justification for bounding the utility function yet exists. 相似文献
18.
19.
A “Pseudo-endowment” effect,and its implications for some recent nonexpected utility models 总被引:2,自引:2,他引:0
Drazen Prelec 《Journal of Risk and Uncertainty》1990,3(3):247-259
This article describes a modification of the Allais paradox that induces preferences inconsistent with two conditions weaker than the independence axiom, namely quasi-convexity (a special case of which is the betweenness axom), and Hypothesis II of Machina (also called fanning-out). These violations can be formally derived from prospect theory by invoking a nonliner transformation of probability into decision weight.I would like to thank David Bell, Vijay Krishna, John Pratt, and especially Colin Camerer for helpful comments and criticism. 相似文献
20.
Expected utility with lower probabilities 总被引:2,自引:0,他引:2
Ebbe Hendon Hans JØrgen Jacobsen Birgitte Sloth Torben TranÆs 《Journal of Risk and Uncertainty》1994,8(2):197-216
An uncertain and not just risky situation may be modeled using so-called belief functions assigning lower probabilities to subsets of outcomes. In this article we extend the von Neumann-Morgenstern expected utility theory from probability measures to belief functions. We use this theory to characterize uncertainty neutrality and different degrees of uncertainty aversion.We are grateful to Birgit Grodal, Salvatore Modica, David Schmeidler, and an anonymous referee for comments, help, and encouragement. Financial support from the Danish Social Sciences Research Council is acknowledged. 相似文献