全文获取类型
收费全文 | 10570篇 |
免费 | 5篇 |
专业分类
管理学 | 1572篇 |
民族学 | 100篇 |
人口学 | 2420篇 |
丛书文集 | 2篇 |
理论方法论 | 491篇 |
综合类 | 287篇 |
社会学 | 4495篇 |
统计学 | 1208篇 |
出版年
2024年 | 1篇 |
2023年 | 4篇 |
2022年 | 6篇 |
2021年 | 3篇 |
2020年 | 7篇 |
2019年 | 7篇 |
2018年 | 1663篇 |
2017年 | 1658篇 |
2016年 | 1086篇 |
2015年 | 38篇 |
2014年 | 40篇 |
2013年 | 48篇 |
2012年 | 324篇 |
2011年 | 1153篇 |
2010年 | 1052篇 |
2009年 | 790篇 |
2008年 | 825篇 |
2007年 | 1000篇 |
2006年 | 8篇 |
2005年 | 229篇 |
2004年 | 258篇 |
2003年 | 215篇 |
2002年 | 81篇 |
2001年 | 11篇 |
2000年 | 10篇 |
1999年 | 5篇 |
1998年 | 1篇 |
1997年 | 1篇 |
1996年 | 29篇 |
1993年 | 2篇 |
1992年 | 1篇 |
1990年 | 2篇 |
1989年 | 2篇 |
1988年 | 8篇 |
1987年 | 1篇 |
1982年 | 1篇 |
1980年 | 2篇 |
1979年 | 1篇 |
1978年 | 1篇 |
1972年 | 1篇 |
排序方式: 共有10000条查询结果,搜索用时 15 毫秒
161.
In this article, we outline a simple and intuitively appealing procedure to derive default priors. The main idea is to regard
the choice of such a prior as a formal Bayesian decision problem. We also discuss Jeffreys prior and more generally the reference
prior of Bernardo (J R Stat Soc B 41:113–147, 1979) from this standpoint. 相似文献
162.
Nicolas Houy 《Theory and Decision》2011,70(4):501-509
We give some characterizations for both the untrapped set and the top cycle choice functions. We link these characterizations
with the well-known characterization of the maximal elements choice function. Our characterizations strongly rely on the notion
of “two-tier domination”. 相似文献
163.
In a homogeneous jury, in which each vote is correct with the same probability, and each pair of votes correlates with the
same correlation coefficient, there exists a correlation-robust voting quota, such that the probability of a correct verdict
is independent of the correlation coefficient. For positive correlation, an increase in the correlation coefficient decreases
the probability of a correct verdict for any voting rule below the correlation-robust quota, and increases that probability
for any above the correlation-robust quota. The jury may be less competent under the correlation-robust rule than under simple
majority rule and less competent under simple majority rule than a single juror alone. The jury is always less competent than
a single juror under unanimity rule. 相似文献
164.
Spyros Galanis 《Theory and Decision》2011,71(4):593-614
We provide a syntactic model of unawareness. By introducing multiple knowledge modalities, one for each sub-language, we specifically
model agents whose only mistake in reasoning (other than their unawareness) is to underestimate the knowledge of more aware
agents. We show that the model is a complete and sound axiomatization of the set-theoretic model of Galanis (University of
Southampton Discussion paper 709, 2007) and compare it with other unawareness models in the literature. 相似文献
165.
Andrea Isoni 《Theory and Decision》2011,71(3):409-430
Several experimental studies have reported that an otherwise robust regularity—the disparity between Willingness-To-Accept
and Willingness-To-Pay—tends to be greatly reduced in repeated markets, posing a serious challenge to existing reference-dependent and reference-independent models alike. This article offers a new account of the evidence, based on the assumptions that individuals are affected by
good and bad deals relative to the expected transaction price (price sensitivity), with bad deals having a larger impact on their utility (`bad-deal’ aversion). These features of preferences explain the existing evidence better than alternative approaches, including the most recent
developments of loss aversion models. 相似文献
166.
Conventional wisdom maintains that youths take risks because they underestimate probabilities of harm. Presumably if they
knew the true probabilities, they would behave differently. We used the National Longitudinal Survey of Youth 1997 to assess
whether differences between subjective and objective probabilities that an adverse outcome to self will occur are systematically
related to a harmful behavior, initiating smoking. We find that youths are generally pessimistic about probabilities of their
own deaths and being violent crime victims. After smoking initiation, youths increase subjective probabilities of death by
more than the objective increase in mortality risk, implying recognition of potential harms. Virtually all 12–14 year-olds
know that smoking causes heart disease. The minority who believe that smoking causes AIDS are less likely to become smokers;
i.e., risk misperceptions deter rather than cause smoking initiation. Messages designed to deter smoking initiation should
stress other disadvantages of smoking than just probabilities of harm. 相似文献
167.
Many experiments have demonstrated that when evaluating payoffs, people take not only their own payoffs into account, but
also the payoffs of others in their social environment. Most of this evidence is found in settings where payoffs are riskless.
It is plausible that if people care about the payoffs of others, they do so not only in a riskless context, but also in a
risky one. This suggests that an individual’s decision making under risk depends on the risks others in his or her environment
face. This paper is the first to test whether individuals’ risk attitudes are affected by the risks others face. The results
show that risk attitudes appear to be less affected by others’ risks than expected, even though the same subjects do show
concerns for inequality in a riskless setting. Interestingly, we find that people prefer risks to be independent across individuals
in society rather than correlated. 相似文献
168.
Anna Dreber David G. Rand Nils Wernerfelt Justin R. Garcia Miguel G. Vilar J. Koji Lum Richard Zeckhauser 《Journal of Risk and Uncertainty》2011,43(1):19-38
We explore how risk-taking in the card game contract bridge, and in a financial gamble, correlate with variation in the dopamine
receptor D4 gene (DRD4) among serious tournament bridge players. In bridge risk-taking, we find significant interactions between genetic predisposition
and skill. Among men with the 7-repeat allele of DRD4, namely 7R + men, those with more bridge skill take more good risks and fewer bad risks, while the opposite is found for less-expert 7R + men. Conversely, skill does not predict risk-taking among men without
the 7R + allele. Consistent with some prior studies, we also find that 7R + men take more risk in the financial gamble. We
find no relationship between 7R + and either risk measure among our female subjects. Our results suggest that the dopamine
system plays an important role in individual differences in risk-taking among men, and is the first to distinguish between
advantageous and disadvantageous risk-taking. 相似文献
169.
Aymeric Lardon 《Theory and Decision》2012,72(3):387-411
In cooperative Cournot oligopoly games, it is known that the β-core is equal to the α-core, and both are non-empty if every individual profit function is continuous and concave (Zhao, Games Econ Behav 27:153–168,
1999b). Following Chander and Tulkens (Int J Game Theory 26:379–401, 1997), we assume that firms react to a deviating coalition by choosing individual best reply strategies. We deal with the problem
of the non-emptiness of the induced core, the γ-core, by two different approaches. The first establishes that the associated Cournot oligopoly Transferable Utility (TU)-games
are balanced if the inverse demand function is differentiable and every individual profit function is continuous and concave
on the set of strategy profiles, which is a step forward beyond Zhao’s core existence result for this class of games. The
second approach, restricted to the class of Cournot oligopoly TU-games with linear cost functions, provides a single-valued
allocation rule in the γ-core called Nash Pro rata (NP)-value. This result generalizes Funaki and Yamato’s (Int J Game Theory 28:157–171, 1999) core existence result from no capacity constraint to asymmetric capacity constraints. Moreover, we provide an axiomatic
characterization of this solution by means of four properties: efficiency, null firm, monotonicity, and non-cooperative fairness. 相似文献
170.
The objective of this article is to investigate the impact of agent heterogeneity (as regards their attitude towards cooperation)
and payoff structure on cooperative behaviour, using an experimental setting with incomplete information. A game of chicken
is played considering two types of agents: ‘unconditional cooperators’, who always cooperate, and ‘strategic cooperators’,
who do not cooperate unless it is in their interest to do so. Overall, our data show a much higher propensity to cooperate
than predicted by theory. They also suggest that agent heterogeneity matters: the higher the proportion of ‘strategic cooperators’
in the population, the higher their probability to cooperate. Finally, our data confirm that higher rewards to cooperation
(embedded in the payoff structure) tend to lower defection. Taken together, our results suggest that the subjects might be
non-expected utility maximizers, dealing with both outcomes and probabilities in a non-linear manner. 相似文献